This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on library shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project to make the world's books discoverable online. It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. Marks, notations and other marginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the publisher to a library and finally to you. Usage guidelines Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing this resource, we have taken steps to prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. We also ask that you: + Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for personal, non-commercial purposes. + Refrain from automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. + Maintain attribution The Google "watermark" you see on each file is essential for informing people about this project and helping them find additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. + Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liability can be quite severe. About Google Book Search Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web at |http : //books . google . com/ OUTLINES OF INDIAN I PHILOSOPHY ! THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDANTA DEUSSEN OF THK University of California. Class ^rt OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY WITH AH APPENDIX ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDXNTA IN ITS RELATIONS TO OCCIDENTAL METAPHYSICS BY DR. PAUL DEUSSEN PB0FB8S0B AT THE UNIVERSITY OF KIEL BERLIN KARL CURTIUS 1907 ■i>( wrtf/Mi PRINTED BY OSCAR BRAKD8TSITBR, LEIPIia PREFATORY NOTES BY THE AUTHOR The first of the two treatises, composing this little volume, appeared in the Indian Antiquary 1902 and is reprinted here with the kind permission of the editor Sir Richard Temple. The appendix "On the Philosophy of the Vedanta'* was originally an address delivered before the Bombay Branch of the Royal Asiatic Society, the 26**^ February 1893. Both treatises complete in some way each other, the first being a very short summary of the history of the Indian philosophy, the second giving a concise idea of that religious and philosophical system, which more than any other is ruling in India even in our days. A fuller account of the subjects treated in this little volume may be found in the following worfcs^ of the same author: Allgemeine Geschichte der Philosophic mit beson- derer Berticksichtigung der Religionen, vol I: Allgemeine Einleitimg und Philosophic des 181772 VI PREFATORY NOTES. Veda bis auf die Upanishads, vol. U: Die Philosophie der Upanishads (translated into £kiglish by Rev. A. S. Geden under the title: The Philosophy of the Upanishads, Edinburgh 1906); vol. Ill: (in preparation) Die nachvedisehe Philo- sophie der Inder. The second edition of the volumes published till now appeared Leipzig, 1906 and 1907. Sechzig Upanishads des Veda, aus dem Sans- krit tlbersetzt und mit Einleitungen und An- merkungen versehen, 11^ edition Leipzig, 1905. — VierphilosophischeTextedesMah&bh&ratam, aus dem Sanskrit tlbersetzt, Leipzig 1906. Die StLtra's des VedAnta nebst dem vollst&ndigen Eommentare des Qankara, aus dem Sanskrit tlber- setzt, Leipzig 1887. Das System des Ved&nta, nach den Brahma- Stltra's des BAdarAyana und dem Eonmientare des Qankara tlber dieselben als ein Compendium der Dogmatik des Brahmanismus vom Standpunkte des Qankara aus dargestellt. 11^ edition Leip- zig 1906. — CONTENTS L OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. PAGE PBEPATOBY BEMABKS S HBST pebiod: philosophy of the BIGVEDA. . . 7 SECOND pebiod: philosophy of the UPANISHADS . 2t THIBD pebiod: POSTVEDIC philosophy 34 II. ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDInTA in ITS RELATIONS TO OCCIDENTAL METAPHYSICS. INTBODUCTION 46 1. THEOLOGY 49 2. COSMOLOGY 62 8. PSYCHOLOGY &S 4. BSCHATOLOGY 61 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY DEUSSEN: PHILOSOPnY PREFATORY REMARKS AMONG the pretexts by which Elaropean idleiieBs tries to escape the study of Indian philosophy we hear most frequently the remark that the ^^ philosophy of the Indians is quite different of indiui PhUosophj from our own and has nothing whateyer to do with the development of Occidental religion and philosophy. The fact is perfectly true; but far from being a reason for neglecting the study of Indian wis- dom, it furnishes us with the strongest argument in favour of devoting ourselves to it all the more. The philosophy of the Indians must become for every one who takes any interest in the investigation of philo- sophical truth, an object of the highest interest; for Indian philosophy is and will be the only possible parallel to what so far the Europeans have considered as philosophy. In fact, modem European philosophy has sprung from the scholasticism of the Middle Ages; me- dieval thought again is a product of Greek philo- sophy on the one hand and of the Biblical dogma on the other. The doctrine of the Bible has again its roots in part in the oldest Semitic creed and in part in the 4 OUTLINES OP INDIAN FHIL030PHT Pendan rdigion of ZoroAslery wMeii, as an intenncdiate link between the Old and ibe New Testament, hns exerdaed more infhienee than is eommonly attrfbnted to it. In this way the whole of European thought from Pythag<»as and Xenophanes, from Moses and Zoroaster, throngh Platonism and Christianity down to the Kantian and post-Kantian philosophy, f onns a eomplez of ideas, whose elements are yarionsly related to and dependent on each other. On the othtf hand Indian phflosophy throngh all the centuries of its de^e- lopment has taken its course vninflneneed by West- Asiatic and European thought; and precisdy for this reason the comparison of European philosophy with that of the Indians is of the highest interest.^ Where both agree the presDmption is that their eonehisions are correct, no less than in a case where two calculators working by different methods arrive at the same result ; and wheafe Indian and European views differ it is an op^i question on which side the truth is probably to be found. 2. Indian philosophy falls naturally into three pe- riods; these three periods are equally strongly marked Periods ^ ^^^ general history of Indian civilisation ofindiaa and are dependent on the geography of PUlotoplij India. India, as Sir William Jones has al- ready remarked, has the form of a square whose four angles are turned to the four cardinal points, and PREFATORY REMARKS 6 are marked by the Hindu Kush in the north, Cape Comorin in the south,, and the mouths of the Ganges and Indus in the east and west. If a line be drawn from the mouth of the Indus to that of the Ganges (nearly coinciding with the tropic of Cancer), the square is divided into two triangles — Hindustan in the north, and the Deccan in the south. If again in the northern triangle we let fall a perpendicular from the vertex upon the base, this divides northern India into the valley of the Indus and the plaiu of the Ganges, se- parated by the desert of Marusthala. Thus India falls into three parts — (1) the Panjab, (2) the plain of the Ganges, (3) the Deccan plateau. To these three geo- graphical divisions correspond the three periods of Indian life: — (1) The domain of the Aryan Hindus in the oldest period was limited to the valley of the Indus with its five tributaries ; the only literary monuments of this epoch are the 1017 hynms of the lEtigveda. Though chiefly serving religious purposes they give by the way a lively and picturesque delineation of that primitive manner of life in which there were no castes, no dgramas (stages of life), and no Brahmanical order of life in general. The hynms of the Rigveda display not only the ancient Indian polytheism in its full extent, but contain also in certain of the later hymns the first germs of a philosophical view of the world. (2) It may have been about 1000 B. C. that 6 OUTLINES OP INDIAN PHILOSOPHY the Aryans starting from the Panjab began to extend their conquests to the east and occupied little by little the plain extending from the Himalayas in the north and the Vindhyas in the south to the mouth of the Ganges. The conquest of this territory may have been accomplished, roughly speaking, between 1000 and 500 B. C. As literary monuments of this second period of Indian life we find the Sanihit&s of the Yajwr-, Sdmor^ and^tftart;at;eda, together with the Br&hmanas and their culmination in the Upanishads. Hand in hand with this literary develop- ment we have under the spiritual dominion of the Brahmans the establishment of that original organisation which as the Brahmanical order of life has survived in India with some modification until the present day. (3) After these two periods, which we may distinguish as **old-Vedic" and "new-Vedic", follows a third period of Indian history — the "post-Vedic** — beginning about 600 B. C. with the rise of the heretical tendencies of Buddhism and Jainism, and producing in the succeeding centuries a large number of literary works in which, together with poetry, grammar, law, medicine and astro- nomy, a rich collection of philosophical works in Sanskrit permits us to trace the development of the philosophical mind down to the present time. In this period Indian, }. e., Brahnianicid, civilisation makes its way round the coast of Southern India and Ceylon and penetrates conquering into the remotest districts of Central India. FIRST PERIOD - PHILOSOPHY OF THE RIGVEDA 3. The oldest interpretation of Natnre and therefore the first philosophy of a people is its religion, and for the origin and essence of religion there is no book in the world more instructive ^"^J^l^, than the Bigveda; Homer in Greece, and the most ancient parts of the Old Testament show religion in an advanced state of development which presupposes many preliminary stages now lost to us. In India alone we can trace back religion to its first origin. It is true that the hymns of the l^gveda also show religion in a later stage of development; some primitive gods stand already in the background, as Dyaus (heaven) and Prithivi (earth); they are rarely mentioned but with an awe which shows their high position at an earlier period. Another god, Varuna (the starry heaven), is still prominent, but even he is in dan- ger of being superseded by Indra, the god of the thunder- storm and of war; and a remarkable h3rmn (iv. 42) 8 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY exhibits a dialogue between Vamna and Indra, in which each boasts his greatness, while the poet notwithstanding the full respect for Varuna, betrays a certain partiality for Indra. This case and many others show that the Rigvedic religion also is in an advanced state of develop- ment ; but the names of the gods considered etymolo- gically and the character of the myths related of them, are so transparent that we are able in nearly every case to discover the original meaning of the god in question. Thus there can be no doubt that Varuna ('OvQavdg) is a personification of the heaven with its regular daily revolution, and that he only in later times became a god of the waters. Other gods represent the sun in its various aspects : Siirya the radiant globe of the sun, Savitflx the arouser, Vishciu the vivifying force, Mitra the benevolent light, th^ friend of mankind, and P^han, the shepherd of the world. Besides these we have the two Agvins, a divine pair who bring help in time of need, and seem to mean originally the twilight with which the day begins and the terrors of the night have an end. A very transparent personification of the dawn is Ushas {*H(&g, Aurora) represented as a beautiful maiden displaying every morning her charms before the eyes of the world. If from these gods of the luminous heaven we pass to the secon.d part of the universe, the atmosphere, we meet here among others Vftyu or V&ta, god of the winds, Parjanya, the rain-god, the terrible PHILOSOPHY OF THE WGVEDA 9 Badra, who probably personifies the destructive and purifying lightning, further theMaruts, the merry gods of the storm and above all Indra, the god of the thunder- storm, who in his battles against the demons that hinder the rain from falling, is the typical god of warfare and thus the ideal of the Hindu of the heroic epoch. Lastly, coming to the earth, there are many phenomena of Nature and life considered as divine powers, but above. aU Agni, god of the destructive and helpful fire, and Soma, a personification of the intoxicating power of the- soma-drink, which inspires gods and men to heroic deeds. This short sketch shows clearly what the gods were in ancient India and what mutatis mutandis they are originally in every religion of the worid, namely, personifications of natural forces and natural phenomena. Man in passing from the brute state to human consciousness found himself surrounded by and dependent on various natural powers: the nourishing earth, the fertilising heaven, the wind, the rain, the thun- derstorm, etc. , and ascribed to them not only will, like that of man, which was perfectly correct, but also human per- sonality, human desires and human weaknesses, which cer- tainly was wrong. These personified natural powers were fuither considered as the origin, the maintainors and controllers of what man found in himself as the moral law, opposed to the egoistic tendencies natural to man. Thus the religion of the l^gveda may teach us that 10 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY gods, wherever we meet them in the world, are com- pounded of two elements — a mythological, so far as they are personifications of natnral powers and phenomena, and a moral element so far as these personifications are considered as the authors and guardians of the moral law. Let us add that the better religion is that in which the moral element preponderates, and the less perfect religion that in which the mythological element is developed at the cost of the moral. If we apply this criterion to the religion of the Rigveda, we must recognize that, notwithstanding its high interest in so many respects, it cannot as a religion claim a specially high position ; for the Bigvedic gods, though at the same time the guardians of morality (gopd fitasya), are mainly regarded as beings of superhuman powers but egotistic tendencies. This moral deficiency of the Bigvedic religion has certainly been the chief cause of the surprisingly rapid decay of the old-Vedic worship ; jthis decay and at the same time the first germs of philosophical thought we can trace in certain of the later hymns of the l^igveda, as we shall now proceed to demonstrate. 4. In certain later hymns of the Bigveda there are Decay of th« numistakeablc signs that the ancient creed Old-Vedio ® Beiigicin was falling into disrepute. A beautiful hymn (x. 117) recommends the duty of benevolence without any reference to the gods, apparently be- PHILOSOPHY OP THE 9IGVEDA 11 cause they were too weak a support tor pure moral actions. Another hymn (x. 151) is addressed not to a god but to Faith, and praising the merit of faith, concludes with the prayer: ''O Faith, make us faithful.^ In a time of unshaken faith such a prayer would hardly have been offered. But we have clearer proofs that the old-Vedic faith began to fade. In a hymn (ii. 12) to Indra, the principal god of the Vedic Hindu, the poet says: — "the terrible god, whose existence they doubt, and ask •where is he*, nay, whom they deny, saying, *he is not', this god will destroy his enemies like play- things" — and doubts like this occur now and then; but even more frequently we meet passages and entire hymns which evidently ridicule the gods and their worship, more especially that of the god Indra. Everybody in the world, says the hymn ix. 112, pursues his egoistic interests, the joiner hopes for broken wheels, the doctor for broken limbs, the blacksmith looks for customers; I am a poet, says the author, my father is a physician, my mother turns the mill in the kitchen, and so we all pursue our own advantage, as a herdsman his cows. This little piece of humorous poetry would be perfectly inno- cent were it not that after each verse comes the re- frain, probably taken from an old hymn: "Thou, Soma, flow for Indra", which evidently means that 12 OUTLINES OP INDIAN PHILOSOPHY Indra also seeks his own advantage and is an egotist like other people. Even more bold is the scorn in hymn x. 119, which introduces Indra in the merriest humour, ready to give away everything, ready to destroy the earth and all that it contains, boasting of his greatness in ridi- culous fashion, — all this because, as the refrain tells us, he is in an advanced stage of intoxication, caused by excessive appreciation of the soma offered to him. Another hymn (vii. 103) sings of the frogs, comparing their voices to the noise of a Brahmanical school and their hopping round the tank to the behaviour of drunken priests celebrating a nocturnal offering of Soma. As here the holy teachers and the priests, so in another hymn (x. 82) the religious poetry of the Veda and its authors are depreciated by the words: "The Vedic minstrels, wrapped in fog and floods of words, go on the stump to make a livelihood." 6. The age in which such words were possible was certainly ripe for philosophy; and accordingly we see Be innin 8 of ^^^^giug in Certain later hymns of the Philosophical ]Rigveda the thought by which here as well as ^^ in Greece philosophy begins — the concep- tion of the unity of the world. Just as Xenophanes in Greece puts above all the popular gods his one deity who is nothing more than the universe consi- PHILOSOPHY OF THE RIGVEDA 13 dered as a unity, we find in the Bigveda a remar- kable seeking and enquiring after that one from which, as an eternal, unfathomable, unspeakable unity, all gods, worlds, and creatures originate. The Hindus arrive at this Monism by a method essentially different from that of other countries. Monotheism was attained in Egypt by a mechanical identification of the various local gods, in Palestine by proscription of other gods and violent persecution of their worshippers for the benefit of the national god, Jehovah. In India they reached Monism though not Monotheism on a more philosophical path, seeing through the veil of the manifold the unity which underlies it. Thus the pro- found and difficult hymn, i, 164, pointing out the difference of the names Agni, Indra and V&yu, comes to the bold conclusion: "there is one being of which the poets of the hymns speak under various names.*' The same idea of the unity of the universe is expressed in the wonderful hymn x. 129, which as the most remarkable monument of the oldest philosophy we here translate? — 1. In the beginning t^ere was neither Non-Being nor Being, neither atmosphere nor sky beyond. — What enveloped all things? Where were they, in whose care? What was the ocean, the unfa- thomable depth? 14 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHT 2. At that time there was neither mortal nor immortal, neither night nor day. — That being the only one, breathed withont air in indepen- dence. Beyond it nonght existed. 3. Darkness was there; by darkness enshrouded in the beginning, an ocean without lights wad all this world; — but the pregnant germ which was enveloped by the husk was bom by the strength of penitence. ( j^r/ ^»"' ) foi^- 4. And forth went as the first-bom K&ma (love) - ^j- which was the primordial seed of mind. — Thus wise men meditating have found out the link of Non-Being and Being in the heart. 6. They threw their plumbline across the universe. What was then below and what above? There were seedbearers; there was mighty striving; in- dependence beneath, exertion above. 6. But who knows and who can tell from where was bom, from where came forth creation? — The gods came afterwards into existence. Who then can say from whence creation came? 7. He from whom this creation proceeded, whether he created it or not. He whose eye watches it in the highest heaven. He perhaps knows it — or perhaps he knows it not. PHILOSOPHY OF THE ^IGVEDA 15 I add a metrical translation^: 1. Non-Being was not; Being was not yet; There was no vault of heaven, no realm of air/ Where was the ocean, where the deep abyss? What mantled all? Where was it, in whose care? 2. Death was not known nor yet immortal life; Night was not bom and day was not yet seen. Airless he breathed in primevality The One beyond whom nought hath ever been. 3. Darkness prevailed at first, a chaos dread; 'Twas this great world, clad in its cloak of nijght. And then was brought to being the germ of all, The One pent in this husk, by Ta'pas' might. 4. And first of all from him proceeded love, JE^ma, the primal seed and germ of thought. In Non-existence was by sages found Existence' root, when in the heart they sought. 5. When through the realm of Being their arc they spanned. What was beneath it, what was in their ken? Germ-carriers beneath! Strivings above! The Qeeds of things were hid, the things were seen. ^ I am indebted for this translation to Mr. N. W. Thomas, M. A. 16 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY 6. Whence sprang the universe? Who gave it form? What eye hath seen its birth? Its source who knows? Before the world was made the gods were not; Who then shall tell us whence these things arose? 7. He who hath moulded and called forth the worlds Whether he hath created it or not, Who gazeth down on it from heaven's heights, He knoweth it; or doth he know it not? 6. The great thought of the unity of all things having been conceived, the next task was to find Attain ts to ^^* What this uuity was. For the attempt detannine to determine it the hymn x. 121 , is especially that Unity typical which, starting apparently from the hymn x. 129, or a similar piece of work, seeks a name for that unknown god who was the last unity of the universe. In the first eight verses the poet points out the wonders of creation and concludes each verse by asking '^Who is that god, that we may worship him?'' In the ninth verse he finds a name for that new and unknown deity, calling it Prajapati (lord of the crea- tures). Thii^ name in striking contrast to the names of the old Vedic gods, is evidently not of popular origin but the creation of a philosophical thinker. Henceforth Praj&pati occupies the highest position in the pantheon, until he is displaced by two other, more PHILOSOPHY OF THE 9IGVEDA 17 philosophical eonceptions — Brahman and Atman. These three names, Prajd^pati, Brahman and Atman dominate the whole philosophical development from the ^igveda to the Upanishads. The oldest term Praj&pati is merely mythological and the transition from it to the term Atman (which, as we shall see, is highly philosophical) is very natural. Bnt it is very characte- ristic of the Hindu mind that this transition is accom- plished by means of an intermediate term Brahman, which was originally merely ritual in its meaning and application, signifying ' 'prayer' '. At the time of the Upa- nishads the name Praj&pati is nearly forgotten and appears only now and then as a mythological figure, while the terms Brahman and Atman have become iden- tical and serve in turn to express that being which, as we shall see, is the only object of which the Upanishads treat. We have now to trace the history of these three terms in detail. 7. It is characteristic of the way in which Indian religion developed that a mere philosophical abstraction such as Prajftpati might put in the back- ground all the other gods and occupy in Praja^u*' the time of theBrd,hmanas the highest place in the Hindu pantheon. PrajUpati in this period is con- sidered as the father of gods, men and demons, as the creator and ruler of the world. Numerous passages of the BrdhmanaSf intended to recommend some ritual DEUSSEN: PHILOSOPHY 8 i 18 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY usage, describe the rite or formula as produced by Prajapati and employed by him in the creation of the world. Such passages regularly begin with the phrase that in the beginning PrajS.pati alone was, that he performed penance and thereby worthily prepa- red himself for creating the different gods, the worlds and the various implements and materials of sacrifice. All the gods depend on him; in him they take refuge when harassed by the demons; and to him as arbi- trator they come if some quarrel about their relative dignity arises. Into these details we will not enter; we will here only point out that the Indian idea of creation is essentially different from that current in the Christian world. PrajApati does not create a world; he transforms himself, his body and his limbs into the different parts of the universe. Therefore in creating he is swallowed up, he falls to pieces, and is restored by the performance of some rite which is in this way recommended. In later texts we observe a tendency to get rid of Praj&pati whether by deriving him from a stiU higher principle, such as the primordial waters, the Non-ent preceding his existence, or by explaining him away and identifying him with the creating mind, the creating word, the sacrifice or the year as principles of the world. In older passages PrajApati creates, among other ritual objects, the Brahman; later passages on the other hand make him dependent on the Brahman. PHILOSOPHY OF THE RIGVEDA 19 8. Every attempt to explain this central idea of Indian philosophy must proceed from the fact that the word Brahman throughout the Rigveda in which it occurs more than 200 times, t^e'sSoiman signifies without exception nothing more than "prayer". Like Soma and other gifts, the prayer of the poet is off ered to the gods ; they enjoy it; they are fortified by it for their heroic deeds; and as man stands in need of the various benefits of the gods, the gods need for their welfare the offerings and especially the prayers of mankind; "prayer is a *tonic' of the gods*'; "Indra for his battles is fortified by prayer" (offered to him); phrases like these occur frequently in the Rigveda; thus the idea became more and more prominent that human prayer is a power which surpasses in potency even the might of the gods. In the moments of religious devotion man felt himself raised above his own individuality, felt awak- ening in himself that metaphysical power on which - all worlds with their gods and creatures are depen- ^ dent. By this curious development (comparable to the ' history of the Biblical Adyog) Brahman, the old name for prayer, became the most usual name for the crea- tive principle of the world. An old Iligvedic question "which was the tree, which was the wood, of which they hewed the earth and heaven"? is repeated in a Brdhinaf:^a text, and followed by the answer: "The 20 OUTLINES OP INDIAN PHILOSOPHY Brahman was the tree, the wood from which they hewed the earth and heaven." Here the term Brahman has become ahready what it has been through all the following centuries — the most common name for the eternal and changeless principle of the world. 9. A better name even than Brahman, and per- haps the best name which philosophy has foond HiBtor7of ^ <^y language to designate the prin- tii6 Atman ^^pj^ ^f ^^ world, is the word Atman, which properly is the exact equivalent of the english "Self". Thus Atman means that which remains if we take away from our person all that is Non-self, foreign, all that comes and passes away; it means "the changeless, inseparable essence of our own Self", and on the other hand the essence of the Self of the whole world. It is not possible, as in the case of Prajd.pati and Brahman, to frame a history of the word Atman. It has no regular development but we see it emerge here and there in proportion as the thinker seeks and finds a more clear-cut expression for the word Brahman to name that being which can never by any means be taken away from us, and therefore forms the only true essence of our nature, our dimany our Self. With this word we have reached the sphere of the Upanishads; we must now say a few words on these most remarkable monuments of ancient Indian literature. SECOND PERIOD PHILOSOPHY OF THE UPANISHADS 10. If we compare the Veda and the Bible we may say that the Old Testament is represented in the Veda by all the hymns ajid Brdhma'^ texts, which ^ ' •^ '' . ' The U|>t- serve the purpose of ritual worship. But, nishiidsof as the Old Testament is superseded by the New, so in the Veda all ritual performances with their rewards are declared insufficient and replaced by a higher view of things in those wonderful texts which, forming as a rule the concluding chapters of each Veda, are called Yedftnta (end of the Veda) orUpani- shads (confidential sitting, secret doctrine). The four Vedas produced different branches or schools, each of which has handed down the common content of the Vedas in a slightly different form. Thus every Vedic. school had, besides the Samhitd, or collection of verses and formulas, a special Brfthmanam as its ritual text^ book, and a longer or shorter Upanishad, which forms 22 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY its dogmatic text-book. Therefore all the Upanishads treat of the same subject, the doctrine of Brahman or At man, and vary only in length and manner of treatment. There are about a dozen Upanishads of the three older Yedas and a great number of later treatises of the same name which are incorporated in the Athar- vaveda. Distinguished by its age, length, and intrin- sic importance is, before all, the BrihadS,ranyaka- Upanishad, and next to it Ch&ndogya-Upani- shad. More remarkable for their beauty than for their originality are E&thaka-Upanishad, Mun- daka-Upanishad, and others. 11. Two terms, Brahman and Atman, form almost the only objects of which the Upanishads speak. Very often they are treated as synonyms, but idea of the whcu a difference is noticeable, Brahman Up&DishadB "' is the philosophical principle, as realised in the universe, and Atman the same^ as realised in the soul. This presupposed, we might express the fundamental thought of all the Upanishads by the simple equation : — Brahman = Atman that is. Brahman, the power from which all worlds proceed, in which they subsist, and into which they finally return, this eternal, omnipresent, omnipotent power is identical with our ft tm an, with that in each of us which we must consider as our true Self, the unchangeable essence of our being, our soul. This idea PHILOSOPHY OF THE UPANI8HADS 23 , alone secures to the Upanishads an importance reaching / far beyond their land and time; for whatever means > of unveiling the secrets of Nature a future time may j discover, this idea will be true for ever, from this man- \ kind will never depart, — if the mystery of Nature is to \be solved, the key of it can be found only there where '' alone Nature allows us an interior view of the world, that is in ourselves. 12. It can be proved that the Upanishads of the three first Vedas are older generally speaking than the Atharva Upanishads ; of the former those chronoio in poetic form belong undoubtedly to a of the UpftnishadB later period than those written m the old and simple prose style of the Brdhmavms; among these again the two oldest are Brihadd^ranyaka and Chandogya, which contain the oldest Upanishad texts we possess. There are passages in Chdndogya which may claim the priority over the parallel texts in Bfihaddraityaka, but in most cases it can be clearly proved that passages in Chdndogya are not only younger than the parallel texts in Bfihaddrafjiyaka but even depen- dent on them; this is evident from the fact that several passages of Bfihaddrai^yaka^ recur more or less literally in Chdndogya but are no longer understood in their original meaning. In this way a careful comparison of the texts leads us to this result that in the whole Upanishad literature there are scarcely any texts older 24 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PEOLOSOFHr ttan ihcme contaiwed in BfikrUp. 1-4 which are coimeeted with the person of Y&jftaTalkya ; these either speak of him as is the ease in 1, 4 and 2, 4, or reproduce his discourses with adTcrsaries and his friend, the king Janaka, and take up the whole of tiie third and fourth book. In these passages we have the oldest germ of die doctrine of the Upanishads and consequently of Indian philosophy. 13. In the Y&jftaTalkya chapters of Briha- d&ranyaka and ther^ore in the oldest texts of the Upanishads we find as the point of depar- usm of tiie tare of the Upanishad doctrine a Tery hold idealism comparable to that of Parmenides in Greece, and culminating in the assertion that the atmoM is the only reality and that nothing exists beyond it. The whole doctrine may be simmied upinthreestatements : — 1. The only reality is the atman; 2. The Mman is the subject of knowledge in us; 8. The dhnan itself is unknowable. 1. All things in heaven and earth, gods, men, and other beings exist only in so far as they form a part of our atman; the dbnan must be seen, heard, known; he who sees, hears, and knows the Mman, knows in it all that exists ; as the sounds of a musical instrament cannot be grasped, but he who grasps the instrament, grasps also the sounds, so he who knows the dtman knows in it PHILOSOPHY OF THE UPANISHADS 25 all that exists ; that man Is lost and abandoned by gods and men, who believes in the existence of gods and men beyond the dtman. 2. This diman is neither more nor less than the seer of seeing, the hearer of hearing, the knower of knowing, in a word the subject of knowledge in us, for this only is our real Self, which can never by any means be taken away from us. 3. The diman, as the subject of knowledge in us, is and remains unknowable in itself. ^Thou canst not see the seer of seeing, thou canst not hear the hearer of hearing, thou canst not know the knower of knowing ; how could a man know that by which he knows everything, how could he know the knower." 14. The idealism of YAjfiayalkya denies, as we «/^ have seen, the existence of the world ; but this denial could not be maintained in the long run. PimthdisooL The reality of the world forced itself on ^- ■ the beholder, and the problem was to recognize it without abandoning the truth laid down by the sage Yftjfiavalkya. This led to a second stage of develop- ment which for want of a better name we may de- nominate Pantheism. Its chief doctrine is that the world is real, and yet the dhnan is the only reality, for the world is the diman. This is the most current thesis in the Upanishads and leads to very beautiful conceptions 26 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY like that in Chdnd. 3, 14 : ''The atmam is my soul in the inner heart, smaller than a barley com, smaller than a mustard-seed, smalls than a grain of miUet; and be again is my sonl in the inner heart, lai^;^ than the earth, larger than the atmosphere, larger thantheheayens and all these worlds." 15. The equation world = Htman, notwithstand- ing its constant repetition in theUpanishads, is not a transparent one; for the dlman is an ab- Bolnte unity, and the wiodd a plurality. Coemogonisni - How can they be regarded as identical? This difficulty may have led later on to the attempt to substitute for this incomprehensible ide ntity another relation between Mman and wojld» .^iftt of causality. This .thepry„opened.tlie.way to a new interpretation_of the old myths of creation which consider the principle, PrajA- pati or whatever it was, as the cause, and the world as the effect. Accordingly the cosmogonies of the Upani- shads teach us that in the beginning the dtman alone existed ; the dtman thought, ''I will be manifold, I will send forth worlds", and created all these worlds. Having created them he entered into his creation as the soul, as theUpanishads never fail to emphasize. We havecalled this standpoint, finding no other name, Cosmogonismi some might propose to call it Theism, but from this it is essentially different. In the theistic view God creates the soul like everything else, but in the case before us the \ PHILOSOPHY OF THE UPANI8HADS 27 8oal is not a creation of the aiiman but the ^Xman him* self, who enters into his creation as the individnal soul. 16. The identity of the highest and the individual \^ aiman^ though perfectly true from the metaphysical standpoint, remains incomprehensible for (^ , Theism the empirical view of things; this view distinguishes a plurality of souls different from each other and from the highest ainMm^ the creative power of the universe. This distinction between the highest soul (paramS.tman) and the individual souls (jivatman) is the characteristic feature of what we may term the theism of certain later Upanishads. It emerges for the first time in KMaka 3, 1, where the two, God and the soul, are contrasted as light and shadow, which intimates that the latter has no reality of its own. 3ut the constantly growing realis- tic tendencies went on sharpening this contrast, until in the Qvetd.9vatara-Up. the highest soul, I almighty and all-pervading as it is, is represented as / essentially different from the individual soul which, \ limited and indigent, lives in the heart, smaller than I the point of a needle, smaller than the ten- thousandth part ; of a hair ; and this, says thetext, ''becomesinfinity". Even \ here God, though isolated and severed from the soul, \ lives together with it in the heart. As two birds living on the same tree, one of which feeds on the fruits of his works, while the other abstains from eating and only looks on; ^ 28 OUTLINES OP INDIAN PHILOSOPHY thus the individiial soul, bewildered by his own impo- tence and grieving, looks for the help of the highest soul, or rather of his own divine and almighty- self. 17. Theism distinguishes three entities^ juDBaIjv:orld«. a creative dtman and the individual diman dependent on him. This duplication of the dtman ne- cessarily had a pernicious influence on one of the two branches, viz., on the highest dtman, who in fact had always drawn his vital force from the soul living in us. Separated from this he became altogether superfluous, since the creative powers attributed to him could be transferred without difficulty to the primordial matter. Thus Ood disappeared and there remained only a primeval creative matter (prakriti) and opposed to it a plurality of indivi- dual souls (purusha), entangled in it by an inex- plicable fate and striving to emancipate themselves from it by means of knowledge. This is exactly the standpoint of the S&nkhya system. We see it shoot up more and more exuberantly in the later Upani- shads, especially in Maitrd^yaniya; but its full deve- lopment is only attained in the post-Yedic period and will be treated later. Before leaving the Veda we have to speak of the moral and eschatological consequences of the Vedic philosophy. 18. In contrast with the Semitic view, the belief in the immortality of the soul has been from the old- PHILOSOPHY OF THE UPANISHAD8 29 est times a patrimony of the Indo-Germanic race. Even in the oldest hymns of the J^gveda YedioEMohai^ the hope is frequently expressed that logybefonthe after death good men will go to the gods to share their happy life. As for the wicked it is their destiny, only darkly hinted at, to fall into a deep abyss and disappear. The first mortal who found the way to the luminous heights of the happy other-world for all the following generations was Yama, who, as king of the blessed dead, sits with them under a leafy tree and passes the time in ca- rousing; the analogous ideas of Jesus when He speaks of sitting at table with Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob in the future state are known to everybody. Different stages of happiness for pious worshippers seem not y to have been a part of the oldest creed. In the course of time this was modified and the belief arose that good and evil deeds find their corresponding rewards and punishments in a future life. A very striking passage of a BrdhmaTjM says: ^Whatever food a man eats in this world, by that food he is eaten in the next world." Among the evils which await the bad man in the world to come we often find mentioned an in- definite fear of dying again and again even in the other world (punarmrityu). This notion of a repea- ted death led on to the idea that it must be preceded by a repeated life^ and in transferring this repeated 30 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY living and dying from the world beyond to the earth, the Hindus came finally to that dogina which has been in all subseqaent ages more characteristic of India than anything else — the great doctrine of metempsychosis. The first passage where this creed clearly appears is in the Bfihaddranyaka-Up.; and it discloses to us also the real motives of the remar- kable dogma. YAjnavalkya, when asked what re- mains of man after death, takes the interrogator by the hand, leads him from th^^^MSsembly to a solitary place, and reveals to him there the great secret: "and what they spoke was work, and what they praised was work; verily a man becomes holy by holy works, wicked by wicked works." This passage together with several others proves that the chief motive of the dogma of transmigration was to explain the different destinies of men by the supposition that they are the fruits of merit and demerit in a pre- ceding life. 19. A religion, after having come to a better view of things, cannot discard the preceding and less per- Deyeio mentof '®®* ^^^V^ of development which have led this Doctrine in up to it. Thus the Ncw Testament cannot the UpanUhadB ...,.- , ^, , « emancipate itself from the Old Testament and its very different spirit. So too the Upanishads, after having come to the creed of metempsychosis, had to retain at the same time the old Vedic creed PHILOSOPHY OF THE UPANISHADS 31 of rewards and punishments in the other world. The two views combined led to a complicated system, which taught a two-fold reward and punishment, the first in the world beyond, the second in a succeeding life on earth. This theory is fully explained in the so-called "doctrine of the Five Fires", an important text found both in Chdnd. 6 and in Brih. 6. This { combined theory of compensation distinguishes three \ ways after death — (1) the way of the fathers, (2) the way of the gods, and (3) the "third place*'. (1) The way of the fathers, destined for the per- former of pious works, leads through the smoke of the funeral pyre and a series of "dark" stations to the placid realm of the moon, where the soul in commerce with the gods, enjoys the fruit of its good works, until they are consumed. As soon as the treasure of good works is exhausted, the soul, through the inter- mediate stations of ether, wind, fog, rain, plant, se- men and womb passes to a new human existence, in which once more the good and evil works of the pre- vious life find their reward. ^ (2) The way of the gods is destined for those who have spent their life in worshipping Brahman. They go through the flame of the funeral pyre and a series of "luminous" stations first to the sun, thence "to the moon, from the moon to the lightning; there is a spirit, he is not like a human being; he leads n 32 OUTLINES OP INDIAN PHILOSOPHY them to Brahman. For them there is no return'^ This passage eyidently teaches that by the way of the gods is attained the highest goal, the union with Brahman. The later system, however, teaching that the knower of Brahman stands higher than the wor- shipper of Brahman, considers this nnion with Brah- man, obtained by worshipping it, only as a step lea- ding to the highest perfection, which the souls united with Brahman obtain only after receiving in it per- fect knowledge. (3) For those who have neither worshipped Brah- man nor performed good works the „third place" is destined leading to a new life as lower animals — worms, insects, snakes etc., after a previous punish- ment in the different hells. Tins punishment in hell, which is a later addition, is not found in the Upani- shads and appears first in the system of the Yed&nta. 20. Transmigration is believed to be just as real as the empirical world. But from a higher point of view empirical reality together with creation and j^l^^^Jj^ transmigration is only a great illusion; for in truth there is no manifold, no world, but only one being — the Brahman, the &tman. The attainment of this knowledge is the highest aim of man and in its possession consists the final liberation. The knowledge is not the means of liberation, it is liberation itself. He who has attained the conviction "I PHILOSOPHY OF THE UPANISHADS 33 am Brahman'' has reached with it the knowledge that he in himself is the totality of all that is, and conse- quently he will not fear anything because there is nothing beyond him; he will not injure anybody, for nobody 'injures himself by himself'. There are, properly speaking, no means of attaining this knowledge; it comes of itself; it is, in the yiew of the theistic Upanishads, a grace of God. He who has obtained this knowledge continues to live, for he must consume the fruits of his prece- ding life; but life with its temptations can no longer delude him. By the fire of knowledge his former works are "burnt" and no new works can arise. He knows that his body is not his body, his works are not his works; for he is the totality of the dtmanif the divine being, and when he dies, *'his spirit does not wander any more, for Brahman is he, and into Brahman he is resolved". *'As rivers run and in the deep Lose name and form and disappear So goes, from name and form released. The wise man to the deity." DEUSSEN: PHILOSOPHY THIRD PEEIOD POST-VEDIC PHILOSOPHY 21. The thoughts of the Upanishads led in the poBt-Vedic period not only to the two great religions of Buddhism and Jainism but also to a Oenenl Surrey whole series of philosophical systems. Six of these are considered as orthodox, because they are believed to be reconcileable with the Vedic creed, the others are rejected as heretical. The six ortho- dox systems are: (1) the Sd.nkhyam of Eapila, (2) the Yoga of Patafijali, (3) the NyAya of Gotama, (4) the Yaigeshikam of Kand.da, (5) the Mimd.nsd. of Jaimini, (6) the Yedd^nta of Bd.- dard.yana. As for the heterodox systems, the most important are Buddhism, Jainism, and the mate- rialistic system of the Gd.rYd.ka6; several others are nothing more than the Yedd^ntic views combined with the popular creeds of Yishnuism or Qivaism. But the six orthodox schools are not philosophical POST-VEDIC PHILOSOPHY 36 systems either in the strict sense of the term. The Mimd.nsd. is only a methodical handbook treat- ing of the various questions arising out of the complicated Yedic ritual. The Yoga is a systematic exposition of the method of attaining union with the dtman by means of concentration in oneself. The Ny- &ya, though it treats incidentally of all kinds of philo- sophical topics, is properly nothing more than a hand- book of logic or better of disputation, furnishing a canon for use in controversies. The Vai9eshikam, giving a classification of existing things under six cate- gories, is interesting enough, but more from a physical than a philosophical point of view. The only systems of metaphysical importance are the Sd^nkhyam and the Vedd^nta; but even these are not to be considered as original creations of the philosophical mind, for the common basis of both and with them of Buddhism and Jainism is to be found in the Upanishads; and it is the ideas of the Upanishads which by a kind of degeneration have developed into Buddhism on one side and the Sftnkhya system on the other. Contrary to both, the later yedd,nta of Bd.dard,yana and ^ankara goes back to the Upanishads and founds on them t]iat great system of the Vedd^nta which we have to consider as the ripest fruit of Indian wisdom. 22. From the Veda to the later systems leads a philosophical development the history of which, for 36 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY want of special documents, must be supplied from the vast bulk of the Mahd.bhd.ratam. Here we The PhiloBophy of the find, in the Bhagavadgitd. (Book vi.), the * Sanatsu j&tapar van (Book V. 1566 ff.), the Mokshadharma (Book xii.) and other texts, the ma- terials which, though in an earlier form than that of the MahdbMratam, have formed the common base of Buddhism and SMkhyam. The philosophical system of the Mahdhhdratami whether we call it epic S&n- khyam or realistic Veddniaf is the common mother of both. Some scholars maintain that the religion of Buddha is an off -shoot of the S&nkhya system, others that Buddhism is anterior to the SdnJehyam. Both are right. Buddhism certainly precedes what we call now the S&nkhya system, but it depends on what is called Sdnkhyam in the Mahdhhdratam. Originally Sd^nkhyam (calculation, reflection) does not mean a certain philoso- phical system but philosophical enquiry in general; it is the opposite of Yoga, which means the attainment of the dtnum by means of concentration in oneself. The words are thus used where they occur for the first time (Qvet. 6, 13), and it is an open question, demanding further research, whether not only in the Bhagavadgitd but also throughouttheMahdhMratam thewoTdsSdnkhyam and Yoga are not so much names of philosophical systems, as general terms for the two methods of reflection and concentration. Without entering into details we may POST-VEDIC PHILOSOPHY 37 say that even in the Mdhdbhdraiam the primordial matter (prakriti) is opposed to a plurality of souls (purusha); but both are more or less slightly dependent onBr ahman as on the highest principle. This is the starting point both of the later SMkhyam which rejects Brahman as the connecting link, and of Buddhism which denies not only God but also the soul. 23. The success of Buddhism in India was due in part to the overwhelming personality of its founder, in part to the breaking down of caste preju- dices by which he opened the road to salva- Baddhism tion to the great masses of the population. Only in small measure did the Buddhism owe this success to the originality of its ideas, for almost all its essential theories had their predecessors in the Yedic and epic periods. The fundamental idea of Buddhism, laid down in the four holy truths, is this — that we can extinguish the pains of existence only by extinguishing our thirst for existence. The same idea is put forth in the 12 Nidd.nas, which by a series of steps go back from the pains of life to the thirst for life and from this to ignorance as the ultimate cause of thirst and pain altogether. We see in these and many other Buddhistic ideas only a new form of what Yd.jfiavalkya teaches in the Bfih.'Up. and if Buddhism in its opposition to the Brahmanical creed goes so far as to deny soul, this denial is only apparent, since Buddhism maintains 38 OUTLINES OP INDIAN PHILOSOPHY the theory of transmlgratioii effected by karman, the work of the preceding existence. This karman mnst have in every case an individual bearer and that is wliat the ITpanishads call the c^^mai^ and what the Buddhists inconsistently deny. A common feature of Buddhism and S&nkhyam is that they both regard pain as the starting point of philosophical enquiry, thus clearly showing the secondary character of both. For philosophy has its root in the thirst for knowledge and it is a symptom of decadence inlndiaas in Greece whenit begins to be considered as a remedy for the pains of life. 24. There are many other features in the Sd.nkhya system which show clearly that it is not, as has been The iMXm generally held up to the present, the original sankhya creation of an individual philosophical ge- ^ nius, but only the final result of a long process of degeneration, as has already been shown. The theism of the ITpanishads had separated the highest soul from the individual soul, opposing to them a primordial matter. After the elimination of the highest soul there remained two principles — (1) prakriti, primeval matter, and (2) a plurality of purushas or subjects of knowledge. This dualism, as the starting-point of the Sdnkhya system, is in itself quite incomprehensible; it becomes intel- ligible only by its development as shown before. The aim of man is the emancipation of the purusha from t\i^ prakfiti ; and this is attained by the knowledge POST-VEDIC PHILOSOPHY 39 that purusha and praJcTiU are totally different, and that all the pains of life, being only modifications of prakritif do not affect the punisha in the least. To awaken this consciousness in the purusha, prakriti unfolds its essence to it anew in every life, producing by gradual cYolution the cosmic intellect (Mah&n or Buddhi), from this the principle of individuation (Ahankd.r a), from this mind, organs of sense, and the rudiments, and from the latter material objects. Theptsrtuha be- holds this evolution of prakfiti ; if he understands that prakriti is different from himself he is emancipated, if not he remains in the circle of transmigration and buffering. The whole system seems to be based on an original assumption that there is only one purusha and one prakfiH by the separation of which the final aim is attained for both. The pretended plurality of f^uru^Ao^ looks like a later addition ; and we do not understand how the one and indivisible prakfiii develops its being before every single purusha again and again to help him in his emancipation, if there always remains an innumerable quantity of unemancipated purushas. If we add to this the fact that all the other elements of the system including the three gun as can be derived from the Upanishad doctrine, we can no longer hesitate to admit thatthe whole Sdnkhya system is nothing but a result of the degeneration of the Yed&nta by means of the growth of realistic tendencies. There seems to have been a time when VedAntic thought 40 OUTLINES OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY lived only in this realistic form of the SAnkhy a; for when the Yoga took the form of a philosophical system it was built up on the very inconvenient base of the Sd.nkhya system, probably because at that time no other base was available. 25. The genesis of the Yedd^nta-system, represented by Bd.darAyana and Qankara^ has many analogies The System of with the Reformation in the Christian Church, the vedanu j^ ^^^ same way as Luther and others re- jected the various traditions of the medieval Church and based the Protestant creed on the pure word of the Bible, so (^ankara (bom 788 A. D.) rejected the changes in Yedic doctrine brought about by Buddhism and Sdnkhya and founded the great system that bears his name on the holy word of the Upanishads alone; but in doing this a great difficulty arose; for the Upanishads, the words of which are in the view of (^ankara a divine revelation, contain not only the pure idealism of Yftjliavalkya but also its later modi- fications such as pantheism, cosmogonism and theism. In meeting this difficulty (JJankara exhibits great philo- sophical astuteness, which may serve as a model for Christian theology in future times; he distinguishes throughout an esoteric system (paravidyA) containing a sublime philosophy, and an exoteric system (apara- vidyft) embracing under the wide mantle of a theo- logical creed all the fanciful imaginings which spring in course of time from the original idealism. The exo- POST-VEDIC PHILOSOPHY 41 teric system gives a description of the Brahman in the richest colom*s, treating it in part as the pantheistic sonl of the world, and in part as a personal god; it gives a full account of the periodical creation and reabsorption of the world and of the never-ending circle of transmigration, etc. The esoteric system on the con- trary maintains with Yd.jliavalkya that Brahman, or the dtman is absolutely unknowable and attainable only by the concentration of yoga, that there is from the highest standpoint neither creation nor world, neither transmigration nor plurality of souls, and that com- plete liberation is reached by him and by him alone who has awakened to the beatific consciousness, ex- pressed in the words of the Upanishads: ''A ham Brahma asmi*' (I am Brahman). Thus the Indians in their Yed&nta possess a theo- logical and philosophical system satisfying not only the wants of the people, but also the demands of a mind accessible to true knowledge only in its purest form. ON THE PHILOSOPHY OP THE VEDANTA IN ITS RELATIONS TO OCCTOENTAL METAPHYSICS AN ADDBESS DEUYEBED BEFOBE THE BOMBAY BBAKCH OF THE BOYAL ASIATIC SOCIETY 25.FEBBUABY 1898. o INTRODUCTION N my journey through |India I have noticed with ^satisfaction, that in philosophy till now our brothers in the East have maintained a very good tradition, better perhaps, than the more active but less contemplative branches of the great Indo-Aryan family in Europe, where Empirism, Realism and their natural consequence. Materialism, grow from day to day more exuberantly, whilst metaphysics, the very centre and heart of serious philosophy, are supported only by the few who have learned to brave the spirit of the age. In India the influence of this perverted and per- versive spirit of our age has not yet overthrown in religion and philosophy the good traditions of the great ancient time. It is true, that most of the an- cient dargana*s even in India find only an historical interest; followers of the Sd^nkhya-System occur rarely; Nyftya is cultivated mostly as an intellectual sport and exercise, like grammar or mathematics, — but 46 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDANTA the Yed&nta is, now as in the ancient time, living in the mind and heart of every thoughtfol Hindoo. It is true, that even here in the sanctuary of Yed&ntic metaphysics, the realistic tendencies, natnral to man, have penetrated, producing the misinterpreting vari- ations of ^ankara's Advaita, known under the names Yigishtd^dvaita, Dvaita, 9^ddhd.dvaita of Ed.md.nuja, Mftdhva, Vallabha, — but India till now has not yet been seduced by their voices, and of hundred VedAn- tins (I have it from a well informed man, who is himself a zealous adversary of (^ankara and follower of RSmd^nuja) fifteen perhaps adhere to Edrntouja, five to Madhva, five to Vallabha, and seventy-five to ^an- kard^chdrya. This fact may be for poor India in so many mis- fortunes a great consolation ; for the eternal interests are higher than the temporary ones ; and the System of the Yedd^nta, as founded on the Upanishads and Yedd^nta Siitras and accomplished by Qankara's commen- taries on them, — equal in rank to Plato and Kant — is one of the most valuable products of the genius of mankind in his researches of the eternal truth, — as I propose to show now by a short sketch of Qankara's Advaita and by comparing its principal doctrines with the best that occidental philosophy has produced till now. Taking the Upanishads, as Qankaradoes, for revealed truth with absolute authority, it was not an easy task \ INTRODUCTION 47 to build out of their materials a consistent philosophi- cal system, for the Upanishads are in Theology, Kos- mology and Psychology fall of the hardest contradic- tions. So in many passages the nature of Brahman is painted in various and luxuriant colours, and again we read, that the nature of Brahman is quite unat- tainable to human words, te human understanding; — so we meet sometimes long reports explaining how the worid has been created by Brahman, and again we are told, that there is no world besides Brahman, and all variety of things is mere error and illusion; — so we have fanciful descriptions of the Samsdra, the way of the wandering soul up to the heaven and back to the earth, and again we read, that there is no SamsAra, no variety of souls at all, but only one Atman, who is fully and totally residing in every being. Qankara in these difficulties created by the nature of his materials, in face of so many contradictory doctrines, which he was not allowed to decline and yet could not admit altogether, — has found a wonder- ful device, which deserves the attention, perhaps the imitation of the Christian dogmatists in their embarass- ments. He constructs out of the materials of the Upa- nishads two systems, one esoteric, philosophical (called by him nirgufid vidyd, sometimes pdramdrthikd avasthd) containing the metaphysical truth for the few ones, rare in all times and countries, who are able to 48 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDInTA understand it; and another exoteric, theological (sagui^d vidydf vydvahdriki avasthd) for the general public, who want images, not abstract truth, worship, not meditation. I shall now point out briefly the two systems, esoteric and exoteric, in pursuing and confronting them through the four chief parts, which ^Ankara's system contains, and every complete philosophical systemmust contain : — I. Theology, the doctrine of God or of the philo- sophical principle, n. Cosmology, the doctrine of the world, ni. Psychology, the doctrine of the soul. IV. Eschatology, the doctrine of the last things, the things after death. C3HAPTEE I THEOLOGY The Upanlshads swarm with fanciful and contara- dictory descriptions of the nature of Brahman. He is the all-pervading ftkd^a, is the pumsha in the sun, the purusha in the eye; his head is the heaven, his eyes are sun and moon, his breath is the wind, his footstool the earth; he is infinitely great as soul of the universe and infinitely small as the soul in us; he is in particular the igvara, the personal God, distri- buting justly reward and punishment according to the deeds of man. All these numerous descriptions are collected by Qankara under the wide mantle of the exoteric theology, the sagu7}d vidyd of Brahman, consisting of numerous "vidy&s" adapted for approach- ing the eternal being not by the way of know- ledge but by the way of worshipping, and having each its particular fruits. Mark, that also the concep- tion of God as a personal being, an icvara, is merely DEUSSEN: PHILOSOPHY 4 50 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDANTA exoteric and does not give us an adequate knowledge of theAtman; — and indeed, when we consider what is personality, how narrow in its limitations, how closely connected which egotism, the counter part of godly essence, who might think so low of God, to impute him personality? In the sharpest contrast to these exoteric vidy&s stands the esoteric nirgur^d vidyd of theAtman; and its fundamental tenet is the absolute inaccessibility of God to human thoughts and words; and again: and the celebrated formula occurring so often in BrihadAranyaka-TJpanishad: neti! neU! viz., whatever attempt you make to know the Atman, whatever description you give of him, I always say: naiU^ na id, it is not so, it is not so! Therefore the wise Bfthva, when asked by the king Y&shkalin, to explain the Brahman, kept silence. And when the king repeated his request again and again, the rishi broke out into the answer: ''I tell it you, but you don't understand it; gdnto 'yam dtmdf this Atm& is silence!" We know it now by the Kantian philosophy, that the answer of B&hva was correct, we know it, that the very orga- THEOLOGY 51 nisation of our intellect (which is bound once for ever to its innate forms of perception, space, time, and cau- sality) excludes us from a knowledge of the spaceless, timeless, godly reality for ever and ever. And yet the Atman, the only godly being is not unattainable to us, is even not far from us, for we have it fully and totally in ourselves as our own metaphysical entity; and here, when returning from the outside and apparent world to the deepest secrets of our own nature, we may come to God, not by knowledge, but by anubhava, by absorption . into our own self. There is a great difference between knowledge, in'\ which subject and object are distinct from each other, and anubhava, where subject and object coincide in ! the same. He who by anubhava comes to the great J intelligence, "aJiam hrahma a$mi'\ obtain» a state called by 99'Ukara Sainrddhanam, accomplished satisfaction; and indeed, what might he desire, who feels and knows himself as the sum and totality of all existence! CHAPTER n COSMOLOGY H^re again we meet the distinction of exoteric and esoteric doctrine, though not so clearly severed by ^ankara as in other parts of his system. The exoteric Ck>smology according to the natu- ral but erroneous realism (avidyA) in which we are bom, considers this world as the reality, and can express its entire dependency on Brahman only by the mythical way of a creation of the world by Brahman. So a temporal creation of the world, even as in the Christian documents, is also taught in various and well-known passages of the Upa- nishads. But such a creation of the material world by an immaterial cause, performed in a certain point of time after an eternity elapsed uselessly, is not only against the demands of human reason and natural science, but also against another important doctrine of the Ved&nta, which teaches and must teach (as we shall see hereafter) the ^'beginninglessness of the COSMOLOGY 53 migration of souls '\ satj^sdrasya andditvam. Here the expedient of ^Ankara is very clever and worthy of imitation. Instead of the temporary creation once for ever of the TJpanishads, he teaches that the world in great periods is created and reabsorbed by Brah- man (referring to the misunderstood verse of the "^ig- veda: 4J^*|ff|»RH*ff t^pfT 5ron#H*W|«iq); this mutual crea- tion and reabsorption lasts from eternity, and no creation can be allowed by our system to be the first and that for good reasons, as we shall see just now. — If we ask: Why has God created the world? the answers to this question are generally very un- satisfactory. For his own glorification? How may we attribute to him so much vanity! — For his particular amusement? But he was an eternity without this play- thing! — For love of mankind? How may he love a thing before it exists, and how may it be ealled love, to create millions for misery and eternal pain! — The VedAnta has a better answer. The never ceasing new- creation of the world is a moral necessity connec- ted with the central and most valuable doctrine of the exoteric Vedtota, the doctrine of Sanis&ra. Man, says (^ankara, is like a plant. He grows, flourishes and at the end he dies; but not totally. For as the plant, when dyiujg^, leaves behind it the seed, vfrom which, according to its quality, a new planf grows, — so man, when dying, leaves his karma, the 64 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDAnTA good and bad works of his life, which mnst be re- warded and punished in another life after this. No life can be the furst, for it is the fruit of previous actions, nor the last, for its actions must be expiated in a next following life. So the Sains&ra is without beginning and without end, and the new creation of the world after every absorption into Brahman is a moral necessity. I need not point out, in India less than anywhere, the high value of this doctrine of SamsAra as a consolation in the afflictions as a moral agent in the temptations of life, — I have to say here only, that the Samsdra, though not the absolute truth, is a mythical representative of a truth which in itself is unattainable to our intellect; mythical is this theory of metempsychosis only in so far as it invests in the forms of space and time what really is spaceless and timeless, and therefore beyond the reach of our understanding. So the Saiiis&ra is just so far from the truth, as the saguTjid vidyd is from the fdrguf^ vidyd] it is the eternal truth itself, but (since we cannot conceive it otherwise) the truth in an alle- gorical form, adapted to our human understanding. And this is the character of the whole exoteric Ye- ddnta, whilst the esoteric doctrine tries to find out the philosophical, the absolute truth. A And so we come to the esoteric Cosmology, whose ^simple doctrine is this, that in reality there is no COSMOLOGY 56 manifold world, but only Brahman, and that what we consider as the world, is a mere illusion (mdyd) similar to a mrigatTiahipM^ which disappears when we approach it, and not more to be feared than the rope, which we took in the darkness for a serpent. There are, as you see, many similes in the Ved&nta, to illustrate the illusive character of this world, but the best of them is perhaps, when Qankara compares our life with a long dream; — a man whilst dreaming does not doubt oft the reality of the dream, but this reality disappears in the moment of awakening, to give place to a truer reality, which we were not aware of whilst dreaming. The life a dream! this has been the thought of many wise men from Pindar and Sophocles to Shakspere and Calderon de la Barca, but nobody has better explained this idea, than Qankara. And indeed, the moment when we die may be to nothing so similar as to the awakening from a long and heavy dream; it may be, that then heaven and earth are blown away like the nightly phantoms of the dream, and what then may stand before us? or rather in us? Brahman, the eternal reality, which was hidden to us till then by. this dream of life! — This world is mAya, is illu- sion; is not the very reality, that is the deepest thought of the esoteric Ved&nta, attained not by calculating tarha but by anubhavoj by returning from this varie- gated world to the deep recess of our own self (Aiman). 66 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDInTA Do 80, if you can, and you will get aware of a rea- lity very different from empirical reality, a timeless, spa- celess, changeless reality, and you will feel and expe- rience that whatever is outside of this only true reality, is mere appearance, is m&yft, is a dream! — This was the way the Indian thinkers went, and by a similar way, shown by Parmenides, Plato came to the same truth, when knowing and teaching that this ; ;' world is a world of shadows, and that the reality is \ I not in these shadows, but behind them. The accord I I here of Platonism and Vedantism is wonderful, but both have grasped this great metaphysical truth by intuition; their tenet is true, but they are not able to prove it, and in so far they are defective. And here a great light and assistance to the Indian and the Greek thinker comes from the philosophy of Kant, who went quite another way, not the Vedantic and Platonic way of intuition, but the way of abstract reasoning and scientific proof. The great work of Elant is an analysis of human mind, not in the super- ficial way of Locke, but going to the very bottom of it. And in doing so, Kant found, to the surprise of the world and of himself, that three essential ele- ments of this outside world, viz., space, time, and causality, are not, as we naturally believe, eternal fundamentals of an objective reality, but merely «ub-. jective innate perceptual forms of our own intellect. COSMOLOGY 57 This has been proved by Kant and by his great dis- ciple Schopenhauer with mathematical evidence, and I have given these proofs (the base of all scienti- ' fie metaphysics) in the shortest and clearest form in my "Elemente der Metaphysik" — a book which ,1 am resolved now to get translated into BInglish*, for 'the benefit not of the Europeans (who may learn German) but of my brothers in India, who will be ;. greatly astonished to find in Germany the scientific substruction of their own philosophy, of the Advaita YedAnta! For Kant has demonstrated, that space, time and causaHty are not objective realities, but only sub- ) jective forms of our intellect, and the xmavoidable ; conclusion is this, that the world, as far as it is ex- f tended in space, running on in time, ruled'thrbughout by causality, in so far is merely a representation \ of my mind and nothing beyond it. Tou"*8ee the"A \ concordance orindian, Greek and German metaphy- f \ sics; the world is mAy&, is illusion, says Qankara; — ' it is a world of shadows, not of realities, says JPtaio; \ — it is ^appearance only, not the thing in itself", f says Kant Here we have the same doctrine in three / different parts of the world, but the scientific proofs of it are not in Qankara, not in Plato, but only in Kant. * The Elements of Metaphysics, translated into English by 0. M. Dnff. London 1894. CHAPTER m PSYCHOLOGY Here we convert the order and begin with the esoteric Psychology, because it is closely connected with the esote- ric Cosmology and its fundamental doctrine : the world is mdyd. All is illusive, with one exception, with the exception of my own Self, of my Atman. My Atman cannot be illusive, as ^s^nkara shows, anticipating the ^'cogito, ergo sum" of Descartes, — for he who would deny it, even in denying it, witnesses its reality. But what is the relation between my individual soul, the Jivar Atman, and the highest soul, the Parama-Atman or Brahman ? Here ^^^kara, like a prophet, foresees the deviations of Mm&nuja, M^dhya and Vallabha and refutes them in showing, that the Jiva cannot be a part of 3rahman (R&m&nuja), because Brahman is without parts (for it is timeless and spaceless, and all parts are either successions in time or co-ordinations in space, — as we may add), — neither a different PSYCHOLOGY 69 thing from Brahman (M&dhva), for Brahman is eham eva advMyanit as we may experience by anubhavay — nor a metamorphose- of Brahman (Vallabha), for Brahman is unchangeable (for, as we know now by Kant, it is out of causality). The conclusion is, that the Jiva being neither a part nor a different thing, nor a vari- ation of Brahman, must be the Param&tman fully and totally himself, a conclusion made equally by/ the Yedftntin 9^^^^^* ^7 t^® Platonic Plotinos, ana by the Kantian Schopenhauer. But (^ankara in hia conclusions goes perhaps further than any of them. If really our soul, says he, is not a part of Brahmanl but Brahman himself, then all the attributes of Brahman,/ all-pervadingness, eternity, all-migthiness (scientifically^ spoken : exemption of space, time, causality) are ours ;', aham hrahma asmiy I am Brahman, and consequentlyj I am all-pervading (spaceless), eternal (timeless), al-j migthy (not limited in my doing by causality). Bui these godly qualities are hidden in me, says Qankara| as the fire is hidden in the wood, and will appeal only after the final deliverance. ^ What is the cause of this concealment of my godly nature ? The Upftdhi's, answers Qankara, and with this answer we pass from the esoteric to] the exoteric psychology. The UpAdhi's are manas and indriya's, prtoa with its five branches, stikshmam (arlram, — in short, the whole psychological apparatus, which toge- 60 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDInTA ther with a factor changeable from birth to birth, with my karman, accompanies myAtman in all his ways Qf migration, without infecting his godly nature, as the crystal is not infected by the colour painted over it. But wherefrom originate these Up&dhi*s ? They form of course part of the mdyd, the great world-illusion, and like mdyd they are based on our innate avidyd or ignorance, a merely negative power and yet strong enough to keep us from our godly existence. But now, from where comes this avidyd, this primeval cause of ignorance, sin, and misery ? Here all philosophers in India and Greece and everywhere have been defective, until Kant came to show us that the whole question is inadmissible. You ask for the cause of avidyd, but it has no cause; for causality goes only so far as this world of the SamsS^ra goes, connecting each link of it with another, but never beyond Samsdra and its fundamental characteristic, the avidyd. In enquiring after a cause of avidyd with mdyd, Samsdra and Upd,- dhi*s, you abuse, as Kant may teach us, your innate mental organ of causality to penetrate into a region for which it is not made, and where it is no more available. The fact is, that we are here in ignorance, sin and misery, and that we know the way " out of them, but the question of a cause for them is senseless. CHAPTER IV ESCHATOLOGY And now a few words about this way out of the Saips&ra, and first about the exoteric theory of it. In the ancient time of the hymns there was no idea of Samsdra but only rewards in heaven and (somewhat later) punishments in a dark region ^adam gahMram), the precursor of the later hells. Then the deep theory of Saips&ra came up, teaching rewards and punishment in the form of a new birth on earth. The Veddnta combines both theories, and so it has a double ex- piation, first in heaven and hell, and then again in a new existence on the earth. This double expiation is different (1) for performers of good works, going the pitfiydnaf (2) for worshippers of the sagunam brah- ma, going the devaydna, (3) for wicked deeds, leading to what is obscurely hinted at in the Upanishads as the triUyain sOidnam, the third place. (1) The pitriydna leads through a succession of dark spheres to the moon, there to enjoy the fruit of the good works and, after 62 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDANTA their consumption, back to an earthly existence. (2) The devaydna leads through a set of brighter spheres to Brahman, without returning to the earth (^r ^ ^niitf^O' ^^* t^^s Brahman is only sagu^am brahma, the object of worshipping, and its true wor- shippers, though entering into this sagunam brahma without returning, have to wait in it until they get moksha by obtaining samyagdarganamf the full knowledge of the nirgunam brahma. (3) The tpMyarifi sihdnamy inclu- ding the later theories of hells, teaches punishment in them, and again punishment by returning to earth in the form of lower castes, animals, and plants. All these vari- ous and fantastical ways of Sams&ra are considered as true, quite as true as this world is, but not more. For the whole world and the whole way of Samsdra is valid and true for those only who are in the avidyd, not for those who have overcome it, as we have to show now. The esoteric Ved&nta does not admit the reality of the world nor of the SamsHra, for the only reality is Brahman, seized|in ourselves as our own Atman. The knowledge of this Atman, the great intelligence: "aham hrdhma asmi", does not produce moksha (deliverance), but is moksha itself. Then we obtain what the TJpanishad say : . ESCHATOLOGY 63 When seeing Brahma as the highest and the lowest everywhere, all knots of our heart, all sorrows are split, all doubts vanish, and our works become nothing. Certainly no man can live without doing work, and so also the Jivanmukta; but he knows, that all these works are illusive, as this whole world is, and there- fore they do not adhere to him nor produce for him a new life after death. — And what kind of work may such a man do? — People have often reproached the Vedftnta with being defective in morals, and indeed, the Indian genius is too contemplative to speak much of deeds ; but the fact is nevertheless, that the highest and purest morality is the immediate consequence of the Yedftnta. The Gospels fix quite correctly as the highest law of morality : "love your neighbour as your- selves." But why should I do so, since by the order of nature I feel pain and pleasure only in myself, not in my neighbour? The answer is not in the Bible (this venerable book being not yet quite free of Semitic realism), but it is in the Veda, is in the great formula ^^iat ivam asi", which gives in three words metaphysics and morals altogether. You shall love your neighbour as yourselves, — because you are your neighbour, and mere illusion makes you believe, that your neighbour is something different from yourselves. Or in the words of the Bhagavadg!t&h : he, who knows himself in every- thing and everything in himself, will not injure him- 64 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE VEDInTA self by himself, na hinasH dimana dtmdnam. This is the sum and tenor of all morality, and this is the standpoint of a man knowing himself as Brahman. He feels himself everything, — so he will not desire anything, for he has whatever can be had; — he feels himself everything, — so he wiD not injure anything, for nobody injures himself. He lives in the world, is sur- rounded by its illusions but not deceived by them: like the man suffering from Umiraf who sees two moons but knows that there is one only, so the Jivanmukta sees the manifold world and cannot get rid of seeing it, but he knows, that there is only one being, Brah- man, the Atman, his own Self, and he verifies it by his deeds of pure disinterested morality. And ^ he expects his end, as the potter expects the end of the twirling of his wheel, after the vessel is ready. And then, for him, when death comes, no more Saxiisdra : H rT'Rl STTTT 4^f|>7 * » f^ I WIT q^ ^T^ ITW »I«W^I He enters into brahman, like the streams into the ocean: he leaves behind him ndma and riSpam, he leaves behjlnd him individuality, but he does not leave behind him his Aiman, his Self. It is not the falling of the drop into ESCHATOLOGY 66 the infinite ocean, it is the whole ocean, becoming free from the fetters of ice, returning from its frozen state to that what it is really and has never ceased to be, to its own all-pervading, eternal, all-mighty nature. And so the Ved^nta, in its pure and unfalsified form, / isithe strongest support of pure morality, is the greatest I consolation in the sufferings of life and death, — Indians, j keep to iti — DEUSSEN: PHILOSOPHY INDEX OF NAMES AND SUBJECTS. Page ^ A. ft^rama's (stages of life) * 5 Agvin's (gods of the twilight) 8 adyaitam (monism) ... 46 Agni (fire) 9 aham biahma asmi (I am Brahman). . 41.51.59.62 Ahankfira (principle of indi- viduation) 39 annbhaya (intuition) ... 51 aparayidya(exoteric8ystem) 40 Atharyaveda 6 Atheism 28 Itman (Self) . 17. 20. 58. 62 ayidy& 60 B. Bfidar&yaoa 34. 40 B&hya 50 Bhagayadgita 63 Bhag&yadgit& Yl .... 36 Bible 21.63 Biblical dogma 3 p»g« Brahman (prayer) = Atman 17 sq. 18. 19 sq. 22. 41. 49 Brdimia9a's (Vedic ritnal works) 6. 17. 21 Brihad&ra^yaka-^pani8had 22. 28. 30. 37 Brih. Up. 1, 4 » » 2, 4 « » 6 • Buddha . . Buddhism . 6.34 . 24 . 24 . 31 . 36 37 sq. Calderon de la Barca . . 55 Qarikara 35. 40 C&ryaka's 34 Caste 5. 37 Categories 35 Ceylon 6 Ch&ndogya-Upanishad 22. 23 Ch&nd. Up. 3, 14 26 n » 5 31 Christian dogmatists ... 47 INDEX 67 Page ChiiBtianity 4 Christian theology .... 40 ^ivaism 34 cogito, ergo sum .... 58 Concentration 35 Cosmogony and Cosmo- gonism 26 Creation 18. 52 QuddhMvaitam (purified monism) ....... 46 Qyetftgyatara-Upanishad . 27 gvet. Up. 6, 13 36 darganam (philosophical sys- tem) 45 Deocan 5 Descartes 58 devayfina 61 sq. Dream of life 55 Dualism 38 dvaitam (dualism) .... 46 dyans (heaven) 7 E. Egypt 18 ekam eya adyitiyam (one without a second) ... 59 Elements (bhilta's) .... 39 Emancipation (moksha) 33. 38 Eschatology . . . 28 sq. 61 sq. Page P. Faith 11 Four holy truths .... 37 a. Ganges 5 Geography of India . . 4sq. Gods, their original nature 9 gop& ritasya (guardians of morality) 10 Gotama 34 Grace 33 Greek philosophy .... 3 gu^a 39 H. Hell 32.61 Him&laya 6 Hindu Rush 5 Hindustan 5 Homer 7 I. I am Brahman 33 t^yara (personal god) . . 49 Idealism 24sq. Ignorance (avidyft) ... 37 Illusion (mfiy&) 32 Immortality 28sq. Indian philosophy ... 3. 4 Indra (god of the thunder- storm) .... 7. 9. 11 sq. indriya's 59 Indus 5 98 INDEX J. Page Jaimini 84 JainiBin 6. 34 Janaka, king 24 Jehovah 13 Jesus 29 Jiyanmiikta(emancipated in life) 63 jtv&tman (indiyidual soul) 27 Jones, Sir William ... 4 E. k&ma (love) 14 Ka^&da 34 Kant 46. 66. 60 Kantian philosophy . 4. 50 sq. KapHa 34 karman (work) . 38. 53 sq. 60 K&thaka-Upanishad ... 22 K&th.Up.3, 1 .27 Eomorin 5 Kosmology 52sq. L. Logic 35 A^yoe 19 Luther 40 X. Madhva 46. 58 Mah&bh&ratam 36 Mahan(aBuddhi, cosmic in- tellect) 39 Page MaitIaya^iya-Upani8had . 28 manas (mind) .59 Marusthala 5 Marut's (storm-gods) ... 9 Materialism 34. 45 m&y& 55. 60 Medieval philosophy ... 3 Metaphysics 45 Metempsychosis (saius&ra) . 30 Mlm&ns& 34. 35 Mind (manas) 39 Mitra (the benevolent light of the sun) 8 Modem philosophy ... 3 moksha 62 Moksha dharmaXn ... 36 Monism 18 Monotheism, of different kinds 13 Morals 9.63 Moses 4 mrigat]:islmik& (mirage) . 55 Muu^aka-Upanishad ... 22 N. neti! neti! . . i . . . . 50 New Testament ... 21. 30 Nidfiua's 37 nirgu9& vidy& (esoteric doc- trine) 47etc Ny&ya 34. 35. 45 INDEX 69 Page o. Old Testament . . . i. 7. 21 Organs of sense (indriya^s) 39 Orthodox systems, six . . 34 P. Pain of life 38 Palestine 13 Panjab 5 Pantheism 25 sq. param&rthika avasthfi (metaphysical standpoint) 47 param&tman(higheBtsoul)27. 59 paravidyft (esoteric system) 40 Paijanya (rain-god) ... 9 Parmenides 24. 56 Patafijali . 34 Persian religion 4 Pindar 55 pitriyana 61 sq. Plato 46.56 Platonism 4 Plotinos 59 Praj&pati (lord of crea- tures) 16. 17sq. prakriti (primordial mat- ter) 28. 37. 38 pr&va (vital breath) ... 59 prithiyl (earth) 7 Psychology . . . . 58sq. punar-mrityu (repeated death) 29 Page pumsha (man, sool, subject of knowledge) . 28. 37. 88 Ptlshan (the nourisher) . . 8 Pythagoras 4 B. R&m&nuja 46. 58 Reformation 40 Beligion 7 Bigveda (Veda of verses) 5, 78q. Bigvedal, 164 13 ' n n,12 11 n IV, 42 8 „ VII, 103 .... 12 „ IX, 112 ..... 11 „ X, 82 12 „ X, 117 10 „ X, 119 12 „ X, 121 ..... 16 „ X, 129 .... 138q ^ X, 151 ..... 11 Rudiments (tanmatra's) . 39 Budra (god of the thunder bolt) 9 S. sagiUL& Tidy& (exoteric doc- trine) 47etc. Samaveda (Veda of songs) 6 Samhit&'s of the Veda . 6. 21 Saipr&dhanam 51 saips&ra 47. 53sq. 70 INDEX Page samyag darQanam . • . . 62 Sanatsig&taparyan V, 1565. 36 S&nkhyam 34. 35. 36. 388q. 45 Savitai (the arouser) ... 8 Schopenhauer .... 57. 59 Semitic creed 3 Shakspere 55 Soma (ritual drink) ... 9 Sophocles 55 flfikshmaiu Qariram (suhtle body) 59 Strya (sun) 8 tapas (heat, asceticism) . 15 tarka (reflection) .... 55 tat tyam asi 63 Theism 27. 38 Theology ....... 49sq. Third place (trittyaiu sth&- nam) 31. 6l8q. Thirst (trish^&) 37 Transmigration 38 Tropic of Cancer .... 5 V. Unity of the world ... 12 upftdhi's (attributions) . . 59 Upanishad (confidential sit- ting, secret doctrine) 6. 21 sq. Ushas (dawn) 8 P«fO V. Yaigeshikam 34. 35 Yallabha 46. 58 Yaruva (god of the starry heaven) 7 Y&yu, v&ta (wind) .... 8 Yed&nta (end of the Yeda) 21. 34. 35. 40. 45 yi^isht&dyaitam (modified monism) 46 Yindhya 6 Yish^uism 34 Yislmu (the vivifying force of the sun) 8 vy&vaharik! avasth& (empiri- cal standpoint) .... 47 Way of the fathers (pitri- y&na) 31 Wayofthegod8(devay&na) 31 X. Xenophanes 4. 12 Y. YfijSavalkya 24. 25. 30. 37. 40 Yigurveda (Yeda of sacri- ficial formulas) 6 Yama (first man, god of death) 29 Yoga .... 34.35.86.40 Z. Zoroaster Oerlag oon Karl Curttus, Berlin W. Die Heldentaten des Dom Christoph da Gama in Abessinien Nach dem portugiesischen Berichte des MIGUEL DE CASTANHOSO iibersetzt und herausgegeben Ton Enno Littmann ord. Professor an der Unlversit&t Strafiburg Der Expedition der Portugiesen unter Christoph da Gama, einem Sohne des groBen Seefahrers Vasco da Gama, nach Abessinien gebiihrt in der Geschichte ihres Landes ein hoher Ehrenplatz. Das Ergebnis der Expedition in den Jahren 1541 — 43 ist nicht als groBe Eroberung anzusehen, es wurde weder eine Kolonie gegriindet, noch wurden Schatze gesammelt, sondem ein christliches Reich, das sich Jahrhunderte hindurch in schwerem Kampfe gegen Heldientum und Islam behauptet hatte, wurde vom Untergange gerettet. Fast ubermisnschliche Anstrengungen hatten jene vierhundert Helden zusammen mit ihrem tapferen Fiihrer, der ihnen in allem voranging, zu erdulden; trotz des imgewohnten Landes, der groBen Hitze, trotz Wassermangels imd schlechter Emahrung, groBer, miihevoUer Marsche imd durchwachter N^chte klUnpften sie mit unerschutterlichem Mute. „Sie waren'S ^^ der abessinische Chronist sagt, „starke und mutige MUnner, die nach Kampf dursteten wie die Wolfe und nach Schlachten hungerten wie die Lowen'^; und ihr Anfuhrer war „ein starker Held, dessen Herz wie von Eisen und Stahl war". Jener Kampf von Europaem in Nordost-Afrika um die Mitte aes 16. Jahrhunderts ermnert uns unwillkiirlich an die Kampfe, die im 19. und zu Anfang des 20« Jahrhunderts von Europaern in Afrika gefiihrt sind, zimial auch an die unserer deutschen Landsleute im Sudwesten des schwarzen Erdteils, wo teilweise ganz ahnliche Bedingungen vorliegen wie in Abessinien. ca. M. 4.50 T Perlgg oon Karl (Eurtius. Berlin W. Berliner Dortr$$e Qeft 1. Dr. »fre6 gorte, ^ ,fflSSd|^SK'iV«n Die DSmer Chinos Dortrfigc, gc^alten im Seminar filr orientaIif(i^e Sprd^en in Berlin Die in 6ent Qeft niedergelegten Hufseii^nungen bajieren auf eigenen, sunt tTeil frem5fpra(^igen, nid^t |e6ermann leii^t jugfinglii^en (Uuellen grd|eren Umfangs. Sie fnt^alten 6as IPiffensiDertefte fiber 5iefe OSIfter, loeli^e burc^ 6ie politifi^en (Ereigniffe ber Ie%ten 3a||re mt\\x in ben TTtittelpunkt h^% allgemeinen 3nterenes gerilAt finb, unb follen bie Kenninis Chinas loeiteren Kreifen oermittein ^elfen. m. ^60 Qeft 2. Dr. Wbert pieftn, &"iUlfr»v«?^t^iHS^^B2s;; Uber Beri*Beri unb i^re Bebeutung fiir tDirtfd^aftli^e unb feriegerifd^e Untemc^mungen in ben tDormen Efinbern Dortrag, ge^alten in 5er Deutfc^en KoIoniaIge{eII{d)aft, Hbteil. Berlin \ ^^ fEB^^ ^^ ^ ^S R B gCfR M AR :CL Crftflpff 23 77 RaCIRMAR28l985 StPl^ ge, CIS. jU' S'62 (viA'l REOgp JIN 21 '83 DEC H&]9fiP^j| JAN 31. 1 1 FORM N@N|;0(!SraU|BB4^ UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY | BERKELEY, CA 94720 GENERAL LIBRABY-U.C. BERKELEY SDDD77=i54t,